登陆注册
10812000000004

第4章

Protagoras and the Pigs Is man the measure of all things?

The pop star Sting, in his efforts to save the rain forests, campaigned in the 1980s for the rights of the Kayapo Indians of the Amazon to preserve their way of life. He successfully petitioned the president of Brazil to establish an Indian reserve, and in 1991 the tribe was granted a protected area of around 25,000 square miles. No sooner had the agreement been concluded, however, than the Kayapo chiefs began to cut deals with mining and logging companies. This made them multimillion-dollar fortunes which they reportedly spent on houses, cars and planes while providing little for their villagers. Despite illustrating credulousness on the one hand and cynicism on the other, this cautionary tale has a positive moral. It shows that human beings strive for much the same things even though we are divided by cultural chasms. A shared fondness for fast food and automobiles has been easier to achieve than globalization of human rights, but it is a start at least. Some moralists suggest that the reason we have not yet attained this panacea is because there are no universal values that apply to everyone in all cultures. Instead, they argue, one way of doing things is as valid as any other, and acts are right or wrong only with reference to a particular cultural system. This is the doctrine of relativism. Today's relativists have gone even further and claim that each individual creates his or her own system of values. The view that 'everything is a matter of opinion' is commonplace. Everyone is entitled to their own beliefs, it is asserted, and no one's perspective is more or less right than anyone else's.

The father of relativism was Protagoras. Born in Thrace in around 485 BC, Protagoras was the first of the ancient Greek sophists, the travelling rhetoricians who taught wisdom for money. The particular brand of wisdom they espoused was the kind that earned Greek gentlemen their points on the debating floor and in the law courts. A good sophist was able to win an argument even if he was in the wrong. The Sicilian rhetorician Gorgias (483-378 BC) maintained, moreover, that knowledge of the subject under debate was unnecessary because every position was false and words have no fixed meaning beyond their use to cajole and persuade. For this reason, the sophists are not thought of as philosophers in the true sense of the word. They should not be dismissed as scoundrels, however, as their ethos was based on a distrust of so-called objective Truth. This was itself a philosophical position, and one that has had to wait until the present day for its renaissance.

Protagoras was arguably the most celebrated sophist of all and amassed a great fortune from the high fees he commanded during his forty-year career. He boasted genuine skill in poetry, grammar and jurisprudence and personally drafted the constitution for the Greek colony of Thurii in southern Italy. He was feted by the Athenians on his first visit to their city, but was exiled in 415 BC for writing the first ever agnostic tract. 'With regard to the gods,' he began, 'I cannot feel sure either that they are or that they are not, nor what they are like in figure; for there are many things that hinder sure knowledge, the obscurity of the knowledge and the shortness of human life.' Protagoras died five years later, just before his seventieth birthday when the ship taking him to Sicily was lost at sea. His books were publicly burned, and only a few fragments of his works survive. We know about his ideas chiefly through the writings of other thinkers, including Plato in whose dialogues he appears, though only in order to be demolished by Socrates.

Protagoras's most famous doctrine was that 'Man is the measure of all things', meaning that there is no truth except that which man perceives. The basis of this view is that nothing in the world can sustain its nature by itself. Instead, things acquire their nature by their interaction with other things. Nothing just is but rather everything is in a process of coming to be, and this coming to be is becoming relative to something else. The colour white, for example, is neither inside nor outside your eyes. Rather, it is the result of an interaction between yourself and something that you perceive. This is held to be the case for all perceptual qualities. If the wind feels hot to me and cold to you, then it is both hot-to-me and cold-to-you. This does not mean that the wind is both hot and cold, as it does not possess a temperature in itself but only in its relationships with those who feel it. The way something is perceived by a given person is a matter for the object and its perceiver and no one else. The fact that another individual finds the wind cold does not mean that it does not feel warm to me. Since things only acquire their specific nature in the way that they are perceived by someone, I can never be said to be wrong in the way that I perceive something. I cannot be contradicted by the nature of the object, as it has no nature without my perception, and I cannot be contradicted by someone else's testimony, since their perceptions have no bearing on my own.

There is an immediate problem here because some people are clearly insane. Someone may think he is Napoleon, but that does not make him the conqueror of the Iberian peninsula. On Protagoras's account, this individual really could be Napoleon to himself, for 'Napoleon' and his psychiatrist are perceiving two different things rather than disagreeing about the same thing. This is because the nature of a thing is determined by an interaction between the object and the perceiver, and I am a different perceiver when I am insane than when I am healthy in mind. Protagoras therefore concludes that none of his perceptions can ever be mistaken and that all false belief is in fact impossible.

At this point in Plato's dialogue Theaetetus, Socrates asks Protagoras why he should stop at the judgements of all human beings being equal. Isn't this unfair on pigs, for example? Why shouldn't the judgements of swine be as valid as those of humans? Protagoras chose to bite this bullet, though he soon spat it out again. He replied that pigs are perfectly entitled to their own opinions, in so far as they can have them. Unfortunately, this would mean that Protagoras's pupils were paying good money to be taught opinions which were no wiser than those of a pig. Yet Protagoras claimed to be an expert on virtue and to teach special knowledge. Since everyone's perceptions are equally true, the sophist argued, wisdom must be something other than making true judgements. Certain opinions are wiser and better to hold than others, he said, not because they are more true, but because they are more beneficial to the lives of those who hold them. Some beliefs will make you more successful in law and politics, for example, and these are the ones that Protagoras imparted for a fee.

Even a teacher as wise as Protagoras, however, might make mistakes or lead someone astray. An apocryphal story tells of how he once gave instruction to a young man on the basis that he would waive his fee should the pupil fail to win his first case in the law courts. The pupil's first case was one brought by Protagoras himself to ensure the recovery of his fee. Perhaps the young man had tried to catch his teacher in a double bind – either he wins the case and does not have to pay, or he loses and Protagoras cannot claim recompense if he is to be true to his word. Assuming that the latter broke his promise, his pupil would not have found the lessons Protagoras had taught him to have been very beneficial. He would more likely curse his gullibility in mistakenly believing that his teacher's instruction would help him win public favour and professional success in court. Nor would he find it any consolation that his confidence in Protagoras had been true for him at the time. In fact, he was mistaken precisely because the truth of his belief was not a relative one dependent upon his perceptions – which had missed entirely his instructor's preference for collecting his fees over keeping his promises. One does not have to besmirch the reputation of Protagoras further to find parallel examples. People often make mistakes about what is good for them. When we are unwell, a doctor's judgement about what will make us better is usually more reliable than our own. This is because a doctor's diagnosis is more likely to be true than our own, and not just true for the doctor but true per se.

If Protagoras had not had a vested interest in defending his qualifications as a teacher, he might have retained without caveat the view that none of us are any wiser than pigs, or at least that no one is wiser than anyone else. There are, after all, many people around today who dismiss the advice of dead, white European males as the biased product of a narrow political agenda. Others prefer alternative forms of treatment to those prescribed in conventional Western medicine. More generous individuals accept at the same time that qualified physicians and DWEMs are also entitled to their own views. The idea is that truth is a matter of taste like anything else, and that it is the individual's right to choose his or her own way of seeing things rather than have someone else's views imposed upon them. There is one way of seeing things in particular, however, that does not fit into this account of truth: namely, the view that relativism is incorrect. If everyone is entitled to their own opinion, what can the relativist say of someone else's opinion that truth is not relative? If this alternative view is to be valid along with all others, then it is equally true that relativism is false.

The case for relativism cannot be stated without paradox. Either relativism must be as false as it is true, or a special case must be made for the truth of relativism. But if it is to be an objective fact that truth is relative, and not a mere opinion, then how is it that truth cannot be more than a matter of taste in other spheres too? The belief that different moral systems can lead to equally stable and happy societies rests on the experiences of travellers and anthropologists. By accepting their findings we endorse the method of observation that led to them. This method, however, is transferable to other disciplines and areas where it might not yield relativistic conclusions. Economists who visited both East and West Germany in the 1980s could easily judge from what they saw around them that a planned economy is not as effective at creating wealth as the free market. Relativism is refuted every time a truth in any area is allowed to be non-relative, and this includes the area of relativism itself. The relativist wants to have his cake and eat it, but one cannot without self-contradiction assert that relativism is objectively true and that truth is not objective. It is fortunate that this is the case, for there are worse things to believe than that you are Napoleon. We would not want to say that someone like Adolf Hitler was entitled to his opinions, or that his were no less true than anyone else's.

The wider conclusions of Protagoras may be self-refuting, but he did hit upon an important insight. This is the thought that every truth requires a measure of some kind. Truths are not true of and in themselves, but are true within a system of thought, or according to certain rules that test their veracity. This would be the case even if there were only one objective measure of truth. It is unequivocally true that two plus two equals four, but only because four is always the result when we apply the rules of addition correctly. The value of a pair of shoes, on the other hand, may be different according to whether they are given to a beggar or a king, but in each case their value is a value to someone. In both cases, the measure of the truth is external to what it evaluates. How we are to evaluate the measure is another issue, and one that does not always have an easy answer. It will certainly not do to say that this measure is simply 'reality' or 'the way things are', since how we divine the nature of things is precisely what is in question.

The problem is especially important in the realm of moral values. People's beliefs about what is right and wrong vary according to the culture in which they live or were brought up. In the Irish Republic, abortion is regarded as a sin even when the mother's life is at risk, whereas in China abortion is regarded as a moral duty performed for the greater good of population control. It is tempting to conclude that the moral buck stops with the particular society we live in. That very thought leads many to preach unconditional tolerance of other cultures. However, the fact that there are many different moral systems does not justify this position, for tolerance is just another social value that may or may not be correct within a given culture. To suggest that it has a purchase beyond that is to admit that there are higher laws above those of the world's individual cultures. There is also a self-refuting element in the argument, since we do not tolerate cultures such as Nazism. Yet Nazism was a fully-fledged moral system with its own standards of right and wrong, its own practices and its own nascent traditions, albeit a system in which racial hatred was a virtue. Cultural tolerance as we understand it in the West may be a very fine thing, but it is logically hollow if we only tolerate the cultures that do not deviate too far from our own. Worse, we sometimes refuse to see certain aspects of other cultures that depart from our own and are tolerant where perhaps we should not be. Many visitors to Soviet Russia and Mao's China accepted that the Russians and Chinese had 'their own way of doing things' at the time, even though that way involved repression and mass murder. And it is not only military dictatorships that deny people their basic human rights, but also many forest-dwelling tribes and religious denominations. Be that as it may, after observing the multifarious cultures of the world most of us cannot help but feel that we should be tolerant towards them and refrain from the worst excesses of patriotic chauvinism. Even if we believe that there is a single correct way of doing things (or at least one that is the best) we might be less than certain that our own culture is the one that has got it right.

At the same time, to argue that all cultures are equally valid is to deny the notion of any kind of moral progress. Five hundred years ago, Europeans were burning each other at the stake in the name of morality. We do not hesitate to condemn such behaviour as wicked. Should we react any differently if people of another culture on the other side of the world were to revive the practice today? What would allow us to condemn them is a notion of what is good for all individual human beings as thinking, feeling creatures. While there is great cultural diversity across the world, it should not be forgotten that there is much that all cultures hold in common. For example, it is difficult to find a culture in which the random killing of children is regarded as a good thing. So rare is this practice that, should we find a people for whom arbitrary infanticide is a cherished institution, we would do better to investigate the practice properly rather than jump to the conclusion that they hold child killing to be virtuous in itself. They may believe, for instance, that the gods demand child sacrifice if they are to make the crops grow. On further investigation, we may find that these people desire the same things that the rest of us do, such as health, wealth and happiness, and merely have odd (or tragically mistaken) ways of going about acquiring them.

Common ground is evident whenever two cultures meet and morality is discussed. If two different cultures had nothing in common in their morality, a moral dialogue could never begin between them. No culture is an island, and to date it has always been possible to establish diplomatic moral relations with newly discovered societies. Even a relationship of mutual hatred provides common ground, for this at least shows that the opponents are considering the same kind of thing in their dispute. Similarly, if there were no degrees of temperature that we could agree upon, where we could both opine that the wind or the water was hot or cold, we would never be able to disagree. It is because we understand and agree upon the terms 'hot' and 'cold' that we can have an argument when we wish to apply them differently in a given case. Disagreements require agreement somewhere along the line.

There may, of course, be tribes of rain-forest Indians who, after receiving the support of a pop star and having seen what other cultures have to offer, would prefer to remain in the state of nature and continue to live on nuts and caterpillars, cheerfully suffering the depredations of malaria and prolonged exposure to the elements. If they are willing to endure this condition in order to maintain their traditions then that is their choice, although we should also ask whether it is the choice of the people or merely of their leaders (who may have the most to lose if the basic structures of society change). If it is what the people want, and what successive generations want, then perhaps they have a moral code that is fundamentally incommensurable with our own. This conclusion would be even stronger if their traditions included infanticide, incest and habitual murder. There may be social systems in which these practices represent the height of virtue, but anthropologists have never discovered them. Should they ever be discovered, and their practices revealed not to reflect mistaken beliefs about gods or crops, then it would be more intelligible to assume not that that was their morality, but that this people did not have morality as a part of their culture.

Protagoras might have agreed with this point. He thought that no individual's beliefs could be reconciled with those of another because they were about quite different things in every case. What he did not realize was that such a state of affairs would prohibit us from ever communicating, for communication requires common ground. Though we may not know what the true, objective measure of things should be, we will not discover it by dismissing the views of others as true only for them. No matter how much respect this attitude shows for the beliefs of other people, it demonstrates little for their capabilities as thinking beings.

同类推荐
  • Shirley(I) 雪莉(英文版)

    Shirley(I) 雪莉(英文版)

    Shirley, A Tale is an 1849 social novel by the English novelist Charlotte Bront?. It was Bront?'s second published novel after Jane Eyre (originally published under Bront?'s pseudonym Currer Bell). Set in Yorkshire during the time of the Luddite unrest—a labor movement that began in 1811-1812 in an effort to protect the interests of the working class—the novel consists of two narrative strands woven together, one involving the struggles of workers against mill owners, and the other involving the romantic entanglements of the two heroines. The novel's popularity led to Shirley's becoming a woman's name. The title character was given the name that her father had intended to give a son. Before the publication of the novel, Shirley was an uncommon – but distinctly male – name and would have been an unusual name for a woman. Today it is regarded as a distinctly female name and an uncommon male name.
  • Dombey and Son(I)董贝父子(英文版 上册)

    Dombey and Son(I)董贝父子(英文版 上册)

    Dombey and Son by Charles Dickens, published in monthly parts from 1 October 1846 to 1 April 1848 and in one volume in 1848. Its full title is Dealings with the Firm of Dombey and Son: Wholesale, Retail and for Exportation. The story concerns of a powerful man whose callous neglect of his family triggers his professional and personal downfall, showcases the author's gift for vivid characterization and unfailingly realistic description. As Jonathan Lethem contends in his Introduction, Dickens's "genius … is at one with the genius of the form of the novel itself: Dickens willed into existence the most capacious and elastic and versatile kind of novel that could be, one big enough for his vast sentimental yearnings and for every impulse and fear and hesitation in him that countervailed those yearnings too. Never parsimonious and frequently contradictory, he always gives us everything he can, everything he's planned to give, and then more."
  • Between Two Ends
  • Lord of the Flies
  • Be the Hero

    Be the Hero

    Author Noah Blumenthal shows that we are all master storytellers. These aren’t the stories we tell around the watercooler or the campfire. They are the stories we tell ourselves—the ones that rattle around in our heads and move us to emotions and actions.
热门推荐
  • 九爻剑传

    九爻剑传

    祝爻十岁以前是个捡垃圾的,二十岁后她再次重操旧业,只是,这一次她是在修仙界里捡垃圾……漫漫仙路,唯有道心,伴我长生。
  • 神尊降世,誓宠掌中宝

    神尊降世,誓宠掌中宝

    前世她是佣兵之王,莫名其妙被一轮诡异到紫月带到不知名的大陆上。在那光怪陆离的大陆上见到了她平生从未见过到巨大的不知名鸟兽。更甚至还见证了一场君王的诞生,一时间天地万兽、万民顶礼朝拜。还没得她完全消化这件事情,她又华丽丽到晕过去了!!再次醒来,甚至连身体都换了个样。靠!老天,你他丫的耍我呢?墨倾染,天印国超级世家—墨家大小姐。人尽皆知的“废物”爹不疼,娘不在,甚至因其为嫡长女而受尽迫害。恶毒姐妹时不时前来找茬,皇子未婚夫厌恶视她为辱,一纸休--情节虚构,请勿模仿
  • 小可爱有点调皮

    小可爱有点调皮

    一场意外,她被赫拉国身份尊贵的王子盯上。“唔……不准亲我。明明说好这一切都是假的!”她误闯了贵族学校的禁地,一不小心惹事,情急下自称自己是赫拉国尊贵的王妃,没想到下一秒却被王子抓住了。王子轻扯领带邪魅一笑:“女人你胆子不小,敢冒充是我王妃?”她:“……”“知道冒充王妃有什么后果吗?!”有谁能告诉她到底发生了什么?她只不过是随口说说而已,为什么眼前的恶魔居然是真的王子!“刚好我缺一个王妃,就那你吧。”尊贵的王子风轻云淡的说着,可她哪知道自己正慢慢地掉入他布置已久的圈套里。日后王妃的生活,她不是被壁咚就是被夜袭!呜.....呜呜这日子没法过了,她要离婚!【甜宠文】
  • 腹黑君王你赢了

    腹黑君王你赢了

    缺德的人什么样?请看她!她的名言是:女子无德便是才!腹黑的人什么样?请看他!他的名言是:面子什么的都是浮云,宠妻才是王道!云端,一个淡然慵懒,缺德毒舌的唯利商人,总是装成儒雅俊悄的小书生模样来卖萌装嫩,蒙骗世人,但骨子里,那份刻骨铭心的薄凉却始终挥之不去!可是他的出现,却乱了她的心弦!夜星辰,一个俊美如斯,腹黑狡诈的男人,唇边带着一抹似有似无的肆意微笑。虽然身份尊贵,心计智谋可将天下玩弄于鼓掌之间。但是,他却将他全部的心思,放在了一个人的身上。为了她,他甘心倾尽所有!他只是一个男人,一个想宠她上天的男人!她遇见他,他找到她。她躲,他找。她逃,他追。当前有狼,后有虎,两边夹击成为过去,当风云起,真相现,生死难猜浮现眼前,他们二人,又会让天地发生怎样的聚变?XXXXXXXXXXXXX某玉得意的笑的分界线XXXXXXXXXXXXX【一.】某女将一个锦盒推到了某男的面前,说,"你不是最喜欢的那个青瓷缎玉瓶碎了吗,这个给你!"某男一边不动声色的欲拒还迎,一边心花怒放的毫不犹豫打开了盒子。盒子刚打开,某男那肆意的微笑就像是被雷劈到一样,眉角还隐约的抽了几下!只见里边平平整整的躺着一整盒的,银票!【二.】"你这是干什么?"云端脑冒黑线,看着动作怪异的某男!"你自己说,我生是你的人,死是你的鬼,现在不要我了,想得美!"某男将自己手上的休书一扬,变随风飘散了!"那你也不用把我绑成这个样子吧?"云端脑后的黑线还在不住的往下流!"我怕你这只狐狸再跑,我现在就要把你带进东洞房,让你补给我一个!"某男轻笑,邪恶的不止一点点!洞房?话说,五花大绑的她,怎么洞房?【三.】"跟我走吧,我会宠你一辈子的!"炮灰握着云端的手,声情并茂!"可是``````"云端欲言又止!"夜星辰那个混蛋接近你是有原因的,不要相信他!"炮灰还在傻傻的说着!"但是``````"云端眨了眨眼,无奈!
  • 魔窟纪

    魔窟纪

    当你一觉醒来的时候发现整个世界都变了,人们都穿着古朴的衣服,唯有一些特别的人穿着沉重的战甲,手中拿着各种各样的冷兵器,只有极少数的人手里拿着一根破木棍,而你也变成了一个名叫萨维斯的佣兵;想要在这里生存下去就得不断的和魔物战斗,面对这突如其来的一切你会如何抉择?是战斗还是死亡?命运又该是个怎样的结局?
  • 康熙大帝:夺宫初政

    康熙大帝:夺宫初政

    《夺宫》是《康熙大帝》的第一卷。描写康熙八岁即位后,在极其险恶的政治环境里,与辅政大臣鳌拜集团的篡位阴谋作斗争的故事。 康熙年幼时异常聪颖,曾拜落第举人伍次友为师,学习封建统治本领。在太皇太后孝庄和侍女苏麻喇姑的支持、帮助下,康熙团结了一批在圈地中破了产的中、下层地主和知识分子,形成了一支拥帝派的拱卫力量。经过多次较量,他终于在十五岁时,智擒了鳌拜,巩固了帝王权力,为清王朝的振兴打了良好的政治基础。
  • 5~7岁孩子爱玩的趣味文字游戏(注音版)

    5~7岁孩子爱玩的趣味文字游戏(注音版)

    5~7岁是孩子智力和体力发展的重要时期,也是培养孩子各方面兴趣的最佳时期。本书写给5~7岁的小朋友,用游戏的方式培养孩子学习语言文字的兴趣,每个游戏都充分考虑了孩子的接受能力,并配有精彩图画,帮助孩子开动小脑筋,学识字、学知识。
  • 影后娇妻,心太野

    影后娇妻,心太野

    外人皆传许博琛冷血无情,不近女色。安暖听到这个说法的时候,冷冷一笑,看向在一旁狗腿地给她揉肩的男人。冷血无情?在她面前,许博琛的血怕是沸腾的,他时时刻刻关注着她的一切,她被陷害,他帮她收拾残局,渣男渣妹嘲笑她,他帮她啪啪啪打脸。不近女色?那那个一到晚上就化身泰迪的人是谁?许博琛在安暖脖颈处蹭了蹭,“暖暖,这是我爱你的表现。”安暖推了推许博琛的脑袋,“我已经要被你的爱意溺毙了,所以你今晚去睡书房吧。”许博琛邪肆一笑,勾着安暖的下巴,“暖暖,你不就是想要换一个地方体验一下嘛,说得这么隐晦,不用等晚上了,为夫现在就满足你的要求的。”安暖……
  • 浮生醉浮生画

    浮生醉浮生画

    本为画里妙人儿,怎得情感二字?浮生若画,画中画外谁是客?几人可曾修成正果?也许他与她本不该相遇且相识。
  • 京门第一暖婚

    京门第一暖婚

    一觉醒来,林瑜发现自己成了睿王世子妃,成了洛阳城无数贵女的情敌。夫君太帅了怎么办!抢夫君的人太多了怎么办!某战神长枪横立,柔情款款:夫人放心,桃花我自己斩,夫君的心和人永远都只属于你!