登陆注册
10812000000005

第5章

Zeno and the Tortoise The use of reductio ad absurdurn

There is a common suspicion in the more refined bar rooms that homophobia, far from denoting red-blooded heterosexuality, in fact belies an inability to cope with one's own repressed homosexual leanings. But if hatred of others springs from hatred of oneself, then by the same token we would expect Ku Klux Klan members, for example, to have a repressed African-American side to their personality. This line of ridicule is known as reductio ad absurdum, which means literally 'reduce to absurdity'. We use this device whenever, instead of arguing that a position is untrue, we examine what would follow if it were correct in order to derive unacceptable results. In ordinary life, ridiculing someone else's argument is certainly easier than constructing a position of one's own. It is no different in philosophy. Where we must wait for the passage of time to reveal the absurdity of a government policy or an over-hasty marriage, in logical argument the process is altogether quicker.

The first philosopher to employ reductio ad absurdum was Zeno, who (according to Plato) was a tall and graceful Greek born around 490 BC in Elea, a town now in southern Italy. Zeno was a pupil of the philosopher Parmenides, who taught that all the many and varied things that seem to exist are actually a single everlasting reality that he called 'being'. He argued that the negation of being, along with any imagined changes it might undergo, is in fact impossible. Only about two hundred words of Zeno's writings survive, but it seems that as a young man he wrote a work of philosophy with which he may not have been entirely pleased and which was circulated without his knowledge. The book did, however, make him famous in faraway Athens. Plato relates that Parmenides and Zeno visited the city together in around 450 BC where they met the young Socrates. Zeno stayed a while, charging noblemen for the privilege of listening to him hold forth. According to legend, he became involved in politics on his return to Elea and plotted to overthrow the city's tyrant, Nearchus. Before the conspirators could act, Zeno was arrested and tortured to death for his treason. Several stories tell of his interrogation. In one, he named the tyrant's friends as his co-conspirators rather than betraying his accomplices. In others, he bit off his tongue and spat it at Nearchus or even leaped upon the tyrant and bit off his nose. These tales are not as far-fetched as Zeno's own philosophy.

Zeno wanted to prove that the multiplicity that the world exhibits was an illusion and that reality was composed of an eternally unchanging oneness. He disavowed any notion of time, motion or any kind of plurality among objects. He attacked our ordinary notions of space and time by assuming their truth and taking the consequences as far as they would go. The result of Zeno's efforts was a collection of forty paradoxes. Most of these have been lost, but three of them in particular have been causing problems for philosophers and mathematicians for two and a half millennia.

The most famous of Zeno's paradoxes is the story of a race between Achilles and the tortoise. Since Achilles is a very fast runner, the tortoise is given a ten-yard head-start. This may not sound terribly generous to the tortoise, but in fact it is enough to win him the contest. When the race begins, Achilles is quick off the mark and soon makes up those ten yards. By this time the tortoise has managed to advance just one yard, which Achilles then covers in a single bound. Now, however, the tortoise has managed to advance a further three inches. Picking up speed, Achilles crosses those inches only to find that the tortoise has moved on an extra inch. By the time Achilles traverses that inch, the tortoise will in turn have advanced some further distance, albeit a very short one. Zeno argues that no matter how fast Achilles runs he will never be able to overtake his rival, because in order to do so he must first draw level with him. This can never be achieved because as long as it takes Achilles some time – however little – to reach the tortoise's position, the creature will have had time to move on a fraction. Though the distance separating them draws ever shorter, it can never dwindle to nothing. The tortoise will therefore remain in the lead for ever.

If this is not frustrating enough for Achilles, things get even worse for him in the paradox of the racetrack. In order to reach the end of a course, Achilles would first have to reach the halfway mark. After that, the remaining distance would have its own halfway mark to be reached. The final quarter can also be divided into two, and so on, it seems, for ever. To get to the finishing line, Achilles would have to travel through an infinite number of divisions of the track. Since each one of these segments must comprise some distance and take some time, however minute, to cross, it will take him for ever to finish the course. Each segment may be very small, but an infinite number of them will make for an infinite distance. Fortunately, or unfortunately, Achilles will not have to worry about running until the end of time as, by the same reasoning, he will never be able to begin running. The first half of the track can also be divided ad infinitum, so before Achilles can cover half the distance he must first cover a quarter of it, and before that an eighth and so on … Since there is no end to these fractions, it will take him literally for ever to leave the starting blocks.

According to the paradox of the arrow, these problems can be put aside because nothing ever moves. The flight of an arrow can be divided into instants, which are the smallest possible measure of time. If the arrow moves during one of these instants, it means that it begins the instant in one place and ends in another. In this case we would not be talking about an instant at all because the moment could be divided further. Once we have alighted on a true instant – a moment that by definition cannot be divided further – then we have a division of time in which no movement can take place. This, however, means that the arrow can never move, as no amount of no-motion can add up to motion. Since the arrow does not move in any single point in its flight, it does not move over the whole flight.

The arrow is the easiest of the paradoxes to tackle. Motion requires time, so it is not surprising that if you take away time and talk instead of instants then you also take away motion. Though the arrow may not move in any given instant, it can still move if motion is defined as a thing's appearance in a different place at a later point in time. The paradoxes involving Achilles and the tortoise are more difficult. They can still be avoided, Zeno argued, by dismissing the very notion of divisibility. If this offends common sense, he thought, then too bad for common sense. It is clearly unsatisfactory, however, to replace one absurdity with another as Zeno does. Fortunately, we can escape from the predicament by using mathematical tools that were not available to the philosopher and his contemporaries in the fifth century BC. We now know it to be a mistake to suppose that a distance composed of an infinite number of finite parts must itself be infinite. If we were to construct a series which added ? to ? to ? and so on for ever, most mathematicians would avow that the total is one, not infinity. There is therefore nothing impossible in space being infinitely divisible. Neither is there a problem with crossing an infinite number of segments of a racecourse in a finite time. By this thinking, then, Achilles can leave his starting blocks and overtake the tortoise unhindered before being shot in the heel with a well-aimed arrow.

Zeno was a 'strong' user of reductio because he took a set of beliefs and derived logical impossibilities from them. But one does not have to come up with paradoxes to stay true to the method. 'Weaker' reductios may involve consequences that are merely unacceptable rather than impossible. A pro-life philosopher, for example, might reject any moral system the tenets of which imply support for abortion even if such support is not explicitly articulated. Or a political theorist might dismiss revolutionary communism because it can countenance the death of innocents as a justifiable means to an end even though its adherents do not hold the right to murder as a core principle. On this level, reductio ad absurdum is little more than an arguing technique, as one man's absurdity might not seem so ridiculous to another. The point goes beyond matters of moral taste – such as abortion – into the purely logical. The German philosopher Immanuel Kant (1724-1804) argued that theft was wrong because such behaviour could not be universalized. That is, if everyone went around stealing things it would undermine the convention of property that makes theft possible in the first place. This reductio would not convince everyone, but it would convince a thief least of all. A similar argument was presented to Yossarian, the hero of Joseph Heller's Catch-22, when he refused to fly in any more bombing raids. 'What would happen,' his commanding officer asked, 'if everyone refused to fly?' 'Then I'd be a damn fool to do any different,' Yossarian replied. The efficacy of reductio ad absurdum depends in a large part upon shared notions of the ridiculous.

An equally important issue for all kinds of reductio is whether absurdities that arise in extreme situations should be allowed to impinge upon beliefs that hold true in ordinary circumstances. For example, many people believe that there is no harm in the occasional use of marijuana and that the law against the drug infringes their liberty. The anti-drugs lobby routinely counters that if the law allowed people to do anything they wanted, society would break down. This may well be true, but it is a consequence far removed from smoking the occasional joint. The charge that someone is taking a point to extremes is normally sufficient to blunt the force of a reductio in ordinary life. For the most part, the further a reductio is taken towards the extreme, the less we feel bound to take notice of its upshot. This may be due to cynicism rather than credulity, since there might be no position that cannot be reduced to some form of absurdity or another.

The other defence against reductio is to claim that one's beliefs are not philosophical ones. That is, they are about specific concerns rather than lofty generalities. So an explanation of homophobia does not have to explain every other kind of hatred. What is true of homophobes may not be true of race-baiting rednecks, though it is possible the two might sometimes be one and the same. However, to defend an explanation is also to defend the method used to construct it. In our original case, this is the dubious principle that all hatred is really self-hatred. Ultimately, for reductio to work it is necessary for both sides to agree on what conclusions count as 'unacceptable'. For that reason, the approach may be unlikely ever to convince the proponents of soft-drug legalization.

同类推荐
  • Community: The Structure of Belonging

    Community: The Structure of Belonging

    The expanded and revised edition of Community tackles the hysteric rise of isolation and fear in a digitally interconnected pgsk.com draws on a decade of putting these ideas into practice to emphasize what has worked and extract those thoughts that were nice but had no durability.
  • Cranford(III)克兰福德(英文版)

    Cranford(III)克兰福德(英文版)

    A rich and illuminating portrait of life in a small town, Cranford has moved and entertained readers for generations. The women of the small country town of Cranford live in genteel poverty, resolutely refusing to embrace change, while the dark clouds of urbanisation and the advance of the railway hover threateningly on the horizon. In their simple, well-ordered lives they face emotional dilemmas and upheavals, small in the scale of the ever-shifting world, but affectionately portrayed by Elizabeth Gaskell with all the weight and consequence of a grand drama.
  • 瓦尔登湖:Walden(英文版)

    瓦尔登湖:Walden(英文版)

    美国作家梭罗独居瓦尔登湖畔的记录,描绘了他两年多时间里的所见、所闻和所思。这部著作区别于先前文学作品的第一个特征,是其对自然巨细靡遗的描摹和引申。大至四季交替造成的景色变化,小到两只蚂蚁的争斗,无不栩栩如生地再现于梭罗的生花妙笔之下,并且描写也不流于表浅,而是有着博物学家的精确。作者无微不至地描述两年多的湖畔独居生活,目的在于通过这次亲力亲为的实验向读者证明:其实不需要很多钱,也能够好好地活着,而且能够快快乐乐地活着。
  • The Further Adventures of Robinson Crusoe(I) 鲁滨逊漂流

    The Further Adventures of Robinson Crusoe(I) 鲁滨逊漂流

    The Further adventures of Robinson Crusoe is a novel by Daniel Defoe, first published in 1719. Just as in its predecessor, Robinson Crusoe (1719), Robinson Crusoe is still as its author. The book starts with the statement about Crusoe's marriage in England. He bought a little farm in Bedford and had three children: two sons and one daughter. Our hero suffered distemper and a desire to see "his island." He could talk of nothing else, and one can imagine that no one took his stories seriously, except his wife. She told him"I will go with you, but I won't leave you." But in the middle of this felicity, Providence unhinged him at once, with the loss of his wife. Although intended to be the last Crusoe tale, the novel is followed by non-fiction book involving Crusoe by Defoe entitled Serious Reflections During the Life and Surprising Adventures of Robinson Crusoe: With his Vision of the Angelick World (1720).
  • Innovative State
热门推荐
  • 卫灵纪

    卫灵纪

    这是一个充满神魔传说的世界。可,传说毕竟是传说传说,神魔在那群人眼中也只是蝼蚁,整个世界都是那群人的后花园,所有人也只是畜生一般。传说,神魔是所有凡人的向往,拥有无尽伟力,可移山倒海,开天辟地,创造一个世界。可在那群人眼中,也不过是小丑罢了。神魔传说一万年后,整个大陆进入了一个新阶段,许多传说也就无迹可寻。他,就出生在这个新的时代,他背负的是整个大陆的命运!这里百族争艳,宗门林立,魑魅魍魉,妖魔鬼怪纵横,他要打破艰难险阻,突破世界的枷锁,完成无上使命!我不是天才,我不是至高强者,我甚至没有强大的背景!但,我要这地,束不住我的脚步,我要这天,留不住我的影!我要踏破这苍穹!他时若遂凌云志,敢笑黄巢不丈夫!
  • 萌妻入怀:男神老公,放肆宠

    萌妻入怀:男神老公,放肆宠

    【本文甜宠欢脱,欢迎各位入坑】男神结婚了,新娘却不是自己,面对这么狗血剧情,时锦锦的决定就是——抢婚,于是整个S市的人都知道季家少爷养了个小恶魔。而时锦锦借着男神的势力,开始横行霸道,各种行为令人发指,众人纷纷上门告状。哪知季少霸气开口,“她的行为都是我惯的!”时锦锦从角落里跑出来对着众人,傲气十足的微抬下巴。“爹地,我妈咪说,他们不服气可以来单挑,绝对实力碾压,但是需要先来你这边交辛苦费。”季少瞥了一眼扮演女儿的小妻子,笑得邪恶。然众人卒。
  • 落天化凡记

    落天化凡记

    人类一直探索破解着自身密码,借助于科技的发展不断突破自身生命条件的限制,追求活的更久,变的更强,不断改变着这血肉之躯......生命进化的终点是什么?智慧生物又该追求怎样的进化之路?宇宙中血肉生物进化到极点为了追求强大的力量逐渐舍弃肉体演化成机械之躯;强大的机械生物进化到极点为了追求旺盛的生命力逐渐虹变为血肉之躯。被史诗级超级进化者掠走的地球人落天卷入了生命体终极进化秘密的漩涡里,为了能保住这一身血肉落天拼命走在生物进化的道路上,只为能回到地球上做回平凡的自己。让我们畅想未来世界的变化,珍爱当下美好生活!
  • 给我一个对手 让我战胜自己(醉美文摘)

    给我一个对手 让我战胜自己(醉美文摘)

    当你缺乏勇气的时候,就要战胜自己的懦弱;当你不够勤奋的时候,就要战胜自己的懒惰;当你需要谦虚的时候,就要战胜自己的骄傲;当你无法宁静的时候,就要战胜自己的浮躁。本书从发现自己—掌控自己—战胜自己—改变自己—超越自己这样一根金线,从人的思想、行为、习惯、性格、人际关系等多方面多角度出发,包括自我定位、聚焦自我、战胜自卑、战胜退缩、战胜命运、摆脱依赖、征服惰性、克服恐惧、逆境成长、征服狭隘、征服固执、打破枷锁、锤炼性情、重视习惯、提高效率、挑战极限、超越平庸、超越竞争、超越思维、超越格局等诸多方面出发,全面阐述了一个人获得成功所需要克服的种种来自于自己的障碍。
  • 收银员不可能这么可爱

    收银员不可能这么可爱

    【日常轻松爆笑文】一只为生活所迫,却内心特皮随时想咸鱼的小萝莉。一名永远都不靠谱的便利店店长。一位风靡全国,却被小萝莉抢了风头的游戏主播。一名沉默寡言,却能用心去和动物交流的少女。一个身怀绝技,既当保镖又当保姆的小弟。以及,他们的日常,轻松,爆笑故事。单身文,全书沙雕风格,无装逼打脸套路。群号:786332387,记得来调戏小萝莉哦!
  • 追妻无门:女boss不好惹

    追妻无门:女boss不好惹

    青涩蜕变,如今她是能独当一面的女boss,爱了冷泽聿七年,也同样花了七年时间去忘记他。以为是陌路,他突然向他表白,扬言要娶她,她只当他是脑子抽风,他的殷勤她也全都无视。他帮她查她父母的死因,赶走身边情敌,解释当初拒绝她的告别,和故意对她冷漠都是无奈之举。突然爆出她父母的死居然和冷家有丝毫联系,还莫名跳出个公爵未婚夫,扬言要与她履行婚约。峰回路转,破镜还能重圆吗? PS:我又开新文了,每逢假期必书荒,新文《有你的世界遇到爱》,喜欢我的文的朋友可以来看看,这是重生类现言,对这个题材感兴趣的一定要收藏起来。
  • 追妻无门:女boss不好惹

    追妻无门:女boss不好惹

    青涩蜕变,如今她是能独当一面的女boss,爱了冷泽聿七年,也同样花了七年时间去忘记他。以为是陌路,他突然向他表白,扬言要娶她,她只当他是脑子抽风,他的殷勤她也全都无视。他帮她查她父母的死因,赶走身边情敌,解释当初拒绝她的告别,和故意对她冷漠都是无奈之举。突然爆出她父母的死居然和冷家有丝毫联系,还莫名跳出个公爵未婚夫,扬言要与她履行婚约。峰回路转,破镜还能重圆吗? PS:我又开新文了,每逢假期必书荒,新文《有你的世界遇到爱》,喜欢我的文的朋友可以来看看,这是重生类现言,对这个题材感兴趣的一定要收藏起来。
  • 我把异界玩成了游戏

    我把异界玩成了游戏

    在下的新书《带着怨气重生》玄幻首发,舔着脸求大家支持一下,谢谢!
  • 覆瓿集

    覆瓿集

    本书为公版书,为不受著作权法限制的作家、艺术家及其它人士发布的作品,供广大读者阅读交流。汇聚授权电子版权。
  • 爱是最美的修行

    爱是最美的修行

    据说,勤修功德可以往生净土。净土在哪里?路远吗?净土的生活是怎么样的,有酒吗?红的或白的?或者只有白菜粉条?有帅哥美女吗?可以相爱吗?有春夏秋冬吗?或者只有常开不败的琪花瑶草?那会有审美疲劳吗?有生老病死吗?或者是长生?那会有一天厌倦生命吗?《爱是最美的修行》是作者在人生旅途中的随手采撷,在世界中看滴水,在滴水中看世界,滴水世界两相映,平凡摇曳是此生!